Skip to main content

Main menu

  • HOME
  • CONTENT
    • Early Release
    • Featured
    • Current Issue
    • Issue Archive
    • Blog
    • Collections
    • Podcast
  • TOPICS
    • Cognition and Behavior
    • Development
    • Disorders of the Nervous System
    • History, Teaching and Public Awareness
    • Integrative Systems
    • Neuronal Excitability
    • Novel Tools and Methods
    • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • ALERTS
  • FOR AUTHORS
  • ABOUT
    • Overview
    • Editorial Board
    • For the Media
    • Privacy Policy
    • Contact Us
    • Feedback
  • SUBMIT

User menu

Search

  • Advanced search
eNeuro

eNeuro

Advanced Search

 

  • HOME
  • CONTENT
    • Early Release
    • Featured
    • Current Issue
    • Issue Archive
    • Blog
    • Collections
    • Podcast
  • TOPICS
    • Cognition and Behavior
    • Development
    • Disorders of the Nervous System
    • History, Teaching and Public Awareness
    • Integrative Systems
    • Neuronal Excitability
    • Novel Tools and Methods
    • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • ALERTS
  • FOR AUTHORS
  • ABOUT
    • Overview
    • Editorial Board
    • For the Media
    • Privacy Policy
    • Contact Us
    • Feedback
  • SUBMIT
PreviousNext
Commentary, Cognition and Behavior

Promisomics and the Short-Circuiting of Mind

Alex Gomez-Marin
eNeuro 1 March 2021, 8 (2) ENEURO.0521-20.2021; DOI: https://doi.org/10.1523/ENEURO.0521-20.2021
Alex Gomez-Marin
Instituto de Neurociencias de Alicante, CSIC-UMH, 03550 San Juan de Alicante, Spain
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Info & Metrics
  • eLetters
  • PDF
Loading
  • cognition
  • connectomics
  • levels of analysis
  • promissory materialism

Significance Statement

Grand neuroscience projects, such as connectomics, have a recurrent tendency to overpromise and underdeliver. Here I critically assess what is done in contrast with what is claimed about such endeavors, especially when the results are “horizontal” and the conclusions “vertical”, namely, when maps of one level (synaptic connections) are conflated with mappings between levels (neural function, animal behavior, cognitive processes). I argue that to suggest that connectomics will give us the mind of a mouse, a human or even a fly is conceptually flawed. Even if we, neuroscientists, do not take our metaphors literally, we should take them seriously.

Imagine that a group of prominent psychologists wrote a paper about the brain of a mouse disregarding neural matters. Measuring attention or perception at unprecedented resolution, these scientists would promise to solve the mouse’s brain (by decree, it would emerge from “mind stuff”). Published in a top cognitive science journal, “The Brain of a Mouse” would inspire the current and generations to come.

Conversely, and in reality, we have it reverse for neuroscience. Mirroring the spirit of the 1986 classic whose running head read “The Mind of a Worm” (White et al., 1986), a recent commentary (Abbott et al., 2020) discusses the feasibility and benefits of mapping the synaptic connections of an entire rodent brain. Entitled “The Mind of a Mouse,” the piece illustrates some of the strengths of the neural zeitgeist. It inadvertently also reveals some of its paradigmatic weaknesses.

What, if anything, could be “wrong” with attempting to map a mouse brain at the synapse level?

In terms of quantity, the authors do the math and set the case: If the connectome of the humble worm were the equivalent in length to the width of a typical airplane seat (by taking 1000 μm3 of brain volume as a 1-cm interval), then mapping the connectome of a mouse would involve covering the distance from Boston to Lisbon. The numbers are indeed daunting. But so is the apparent lack of need for conceptual work on the subject. What is there to say about the qualitative nature of the challenge? Borrowing from the Boston-Lisbon analogy, would knowing how far both cities are reveal anything about the purpose of the trip? One could photograph every inch along the way and still remain ignorant about whether one traveled to Lisbon to attend a wedding or a funeral.

This leads to a kind of scientific déjà vu. As molecular biologists claim to have explained the nature of life in molecular terms, so do neuroscientists seek to explain the nature of mind in neural terms. Connectomics borrows the élan of genomics and directs it to the brain. A connectome (Hagmann, 2005; Sporns et al., 2005) is a comprehensive map of neural connections in the brain, the nervous system architecture at single-synapse resolution. Regarded as the logical (but not biological) analog of an electronic circuit diagram, the quest is not without major caveats (Lazebnik, 2002; Jonas and Kording, 2017). Contrary to what some might still think, genes alone do not determine the development of biological form (arguably one of the two fundamentally unsolved problems in biology, which the latter Watson thought DNA could solve), nor does neural activity by itself give rise to behavior, cognition, mind or the c-word (arguably the other fundamentally unsolved problem, which the latter Crick sought to crack).

Nonetheless, “omics” missions are pellucid: sequence the genome, map the connectome. A theoretical vacuum is supplemented with a methodological tour de force, whereby new technology plus big datasets are expected to turn low-level descriptions into high-level explanations. This is combined with the misguided suggestion that the only way to answer big questions is via “big science” (occasionally providing big insights), with its tripartite structure of big money, big tools, big data.

Thus, even if we could, it is unclear whether we should have such a connectome. Before answering how, it may be wise asking what for.

Let us step back. What did we really learn from the worm’s connectome, especially compared with what was promised (and spent)? What did the connectome actually explain? Some may claim that we learned a lot, others that we learned very little. This actually opens a can of worms. If the goal ever was to understand the nematode’s behavior (not to mention its mind, which entails an extra conceptual pirouette), we certainly learned virtually nothing. It is argued that the worm turned out to be “surprisingly” more complex than the funded grantees thought. And yet, to claim that what we learned is that we could not learn much sounds rather cynical.

Despite their particularities, a similar story can be told for the history of grand initiatives such as the Human Genome Project (Hall, 2010; Science, 2001) or the Human Brain Project (Theil, 2015). We have been here before. What the advocates of the genome assured (and failed to deliver) for life, some proponents of the connectome vaticinate for mind: revolutionary understanding and medical miracles. Apparently, “similar objections were voiced when the Human Genome Project, now widely viewed as a success, was first proposed” (Lichtman and Sanes, 2008; my italics). As it turns out, hard sells are bought more easily (Bennet, 2013). Politely said, “faced with the need to convince skeptical funders, they needed to present an optimistic view” (Lichtman and Sanes, 2008). In a word, overpromise and underdeliver.

We have had the complete connectome (and genome) of this fantastic humble nematode for many years now. No doubt, such information has helped neuroscientists when designing and interpreting their experiments. But, what does it tell us, precisely, about “the mind of the worm”? Arguably zilch. How come? Because there are too many gaps to bridge, too many levels to connect, too many covert assumptions to spell out.

Synapses are obviously not all you need to characterize a circuit. One needs to know the nature of the connections, as well as cell types. A connectome does not map neural signals either. And, despite the phrase “functional connectivity,” one does not get circuit function from circuit structure, nor causality (Mehler and Kording, 2018). Neurobiology is profuse with instances where the same circuit gives rise to different functions, and where the same function is accomplished by different circuits (Gunaratne et al., 2017). One-to-one mappings are elusive. Moreover, neuromodulation, the biochemical regulation of neural excitability, is pervasive and crucial (Marder, 2012). In addition, the behavior of organisms is not the behavior of their brains. Central nervous systems inhabit species-specific bodies (Chiel and Beer, 1997) that enact a world (Thompson and Cosmelli, 2011). And such environments, rather than being mere physical surroundings, are idiosyncratically meaningful to each organism (von Uexküll, 1909). Brains are overrated (Ghazanfar, 2018). Furthermore, there is variability within (Lu et al., 2009) and across (Witvliet et al., 2020) individual connectomes. Experience constantly reshapes neural circuits. Development matters. Animals are embodied historical beings in a process of extensive becoming (Gomez-Marin and Ghazanfar, 2019).

All these dynamical aspects are nowhere to be found in those maps. Again, structure does matter [even to Marrian functionalists (Marr, 1982), since substrate-independence is not substrate-irrelevance], but the connectomics canon misses so many connections. A few neurons in the lobster’s stomach (or, basically, wherever one looks) attest such difficulties too (Marder and Bucher, 2007). Biology needs technology, but biological unknowns are not an engineering problem. Nor is neuroscience primarily a data science problem either, despite the daunting task of collecting, processing and making sense of such large volumes (Lichtman et al., 2014). This brings us to another set of challenges. How are we, humans, going to make sense of such data? Hopefully, we are not going to leave its interpretation also to machines. One should be prudent not to add to the hypes and hopes of omics those of AI. Wondrous maps may be comprehensive at the expense of being comprehensible. The difference between complicated and complex not of degree but of kind.

And yet, this is already-well-known and dully acknowledged. Deeming the above observations a collection of strawman arguments is somewhat a strawman argument itself since, even when acknowledged de jure, such biological points are not granted de facto. In other words, research is planned, executed and interpreted without having them into account, until one asks about their importance. And so, extrapolating from the wording of the worm literature, we step into a disappointing infinite regress. We now face the same but also a different challenge: forget the nematode, the time seems to be ripe to map a mammalian brain.

No doubt, this adventure demands fascinating new tools, the usual spur to keep the enterprise running. The collaborative aspect is essential and refreshing. Plus, the more species studied, the better. Not only does neuroscience need behavior (Krakauer et al., 2017; Niv, 2020) but also comparative evolutionary accounts (Laurent, 2016; Cisek, 2019). So far so good. And yet, the rationale of the undertaking is sustained by grand vows articulated with a rhetoric surfeited with “filler verbs” (underly, determine, unravel) and “killer adjectives” (transformative, profound, disruptive, mechanistic, revolutionary). Promethean neuroscience becomes an instantiation of the Sisyphean myth (Hadot, 2006).

Do we need to get the connectome before we realize it cannot bridge the other levels of organization?

Let us be clear, there is a priori nothing wrong with industriously performing detailed biological work. Detailed neural mappings in organisms such as the larval fruit fly (Eichler et al., 2017), adult fruit fly (Zheng et al., 2018; Hulse et al., 2020; Li et al., 2020; Scheffer et al., 2020), larval zebrafish (Hildebrand et al., 2017), or mice (Oh et al.,2014; Winnubst et al., 2019; Coletta et al., 2020) shed light onto facts and principles of neural organization. Connectomes can indeed be very useful to understand how simple motor patterns are generated. This is not a black or white issue, but one of subtle grays. One should not subscribe to the all-easy and arrogant critique of biology as mere stamp-collecting. Neither blindly endorse the collection of data for its own sake. The sleight of mind takes place when maps at one level (i.e., synaptic connections) are conflated with mappings between levels (neural function, animal behavior, cognitive processes), namely, when the results are “horizontal” but the conclusions “vertical.”

How is a wiring diagram equated with an organism’s mind?!

Both science and science fiction tend to localize individuality in the brain. In other words, the brain would be “the somatic limit of the self” (Vidal, 2016). Upon transplantation, it is thought that one’s brain would simply miss (like a lover) one’s body, while one would remain essentially the same. And yet, the difference between having and being a brain is crucial (Gabriel, 2017). If the connectome makes me who I am (Seung, 2012), then skipping morning coffee makes me who I am not. The mind is not connecting the dots.

When pressed, the forerunners of the connectome (and of “promisomics,” for that matter) would remark that one should not take certain figures of speech literally. Perhaps not seriously either? The proclaimers of the “Map’ Em All” mantra concede that a future connectome would inform and constrain future work. This is either a splendid truism (the past will somewhat influence the future) or unfathomable futurology (one will have to wait for the future to know), or perhaps both, as a scientific version of the “oracular illusion” (Rosset, 2012). It is a no-brainer that, with or without a question in mind, present research shall enable future research, either as its main goal or as an unexpected consequence of other goals. The insistence that brain function is determined (in part) by how neurons are connected is conceded (notwithstanding logical fallacies, such as those concealed in “necessity and sufficiency” claims; Gomez-Marin, 2017; Yoshihara and Yoshihara, 2018). But this is also true for hormones, microbiota, muscles, or the environment. They all influence brain activity. Do we also need the metabolome, the “ethome,” the “bodyome,” and even the “worldome”? Why? Why not? What would we do with them? An infinite resolution map is worse than the territory.

At the risk of oversimplifying the argument of those determined to obtain the connectome (or making it on their behalf), perhaps the core rationale is this: since we do not know what details matter, all details matter. Omics is the limit case of callow reductionism when the components table tends to infinity. “Without knowing the parts list and what is connected to what, how could one ever really know how it works?” (Morgan and Lichtman, 2013). Should we then collect everything we can, just in case? Can we know what is inessential only later? It is indeed futile and even foolish to argue against more (and better) data in principle, but what about in practice? Producing tons of high-quality “bricks” does not necessarily confer high-quality “buildings” (Forscher, 1963). Can we do without hypotheses? And without theory? For instance, in contrast with the idea that to fully understand one must measure fully, one finds in the notion of coarse-graining insightful overtones for downward causation (Flack, 2017) or causal emergence (Hoel et al., 2013). In other words, coarse-grained objects are not mere lossy summaries of fundamental “building blocks” (once conceived as the ultimate bottom of nature but which dissolve at the ultramicroscale, as physicists discovered more than a century ago, but whose premodern attitude biologists still seek to imitate). The belief that what one sees under a microscope is realer than what we see with bare eyes is an ingrained bias of thought (Capek, 1971). Theoretical work is the art of discarding information, to make informed decisions about what is signal and what is noise. In fact, omitting certain details is not only possible but desirable. Leaving technological challenges and sociological matters aside, the key theoretical question is whether we must collect each and every detail, and why.

Never mind. Unexpected results and fascinating discoveries along the way will help us get through the unfulfilled promises. And, anyhow, if we do not map it, somebody else will. In a kind of perfectly sealed reasoning, it seems that the only way to know whether we need the connectome is to actually have it. The main argument is in fact an assertion: the connectome is mandatory if we stand any chance of understanding the function of nervous systems, the behavior of organisms, and animal minds. Rather than asking why, pioneers prefer to ask why not, articulating and subsequently countering some of the main arguments against connectomics (Morgan and Lichtman, 2013). Where is the burden of proof? Physics pioneered and thrived with “big science” approaches indeed, but it never occurred to a sensible cosmologist to measure the position and momentum of all the atoms in the galaxy, nor to meteorologists to track the trajectories of each and every water droplet falling from a cloud. Again, any map is in principle useful, but how much detail is too much detail?

The first sentence of the abstract of the aforementioned piece (Abbott et al., 2020) is worth pondering: “Large scientific projects in genomics and astronomy are influential not because they answer any single question but because they enable investigation of continuously arising new questions from the same data-rich sources.” But note that any project, and large ones in particular, given the limited nature of scientific funding, attention, and talent, preclude the realization of other projects. Moreover, and borrowing the concept from social media, “audience capture” can easily turn against oneself: writing what you think grant agencies want to read, rather than what you want to do, reinforces a vicious intellectual cycle. Leaving these inconvenient remarks aside, such kind of hypothesis-enabling research should, at least, refrain from grand vague pledges. The last sentence of the paper hammers it: “we predict that a whole-brain mammalian connectome will generate entirely new and unanticipated questions about the nervous system and perhaps represent a turning point in the pursuit of understanding what makes us the unique animals we are.” Well, yes, or perhaps not at all. Who knows? That time will tell is not an argument. To issue promissory notes on top of promissory notes is rather immoderate.

Let us go back to the Human Genome Project. A decade after its launch in 1990, President Bill Clinton proclaimed: “Today we are learning the language in which God created life” (Collins, 2006). If nature is a book, physicists use to read it mathematical language. In turn, molecular biologists pretend to decipher the book of life as if written in genetic code (Kay, 2000). The book of mind would reveal its secrets to neuroscientists in neural jargon. And yet, even when having all the letters, we often remain lost in translation. Text and context are two different things. To Clinton’s statement, editors of eminent journals added: “We will have extra limbs, if we want them, and maybe even wings to fly” (Nature, 2011). Forecasts tell you no less about the forecaster than about the future. Of course, as always, the best is yet to come… The allure and grandeur of “big biology,” the quests for Holy Grails and Rosetta Stones are crowded with implausible pledges. The declaration of what one will do is conflated with the assurance of what will happen. The so-called discovery-driven research, confidently not hypothesis-driven, is often chiefly technology-driven. When academia plays business, when creative scientific discovery adopts the modus operandi of neoliberalism, the resulting creature becomes rather Frankensteinian (Lazebnik, 2018).

To recap, my position should not be taken as a plea against scientific pluralism. Quite the contrary. Nor do I pretend to tell others what to do. I am challenging what is claimed or suggested, especially when the gap between the data and its interpretation, between what is promised and what is delivered, is as great as unbridged. Any approach has limitations. But neuroscientists (of course, far from being considered a homogeneous group) have better work to do than explaining the mind away. Nowadays scientific writing is suffused with “promissory materialism” (Popper and Eccles, 1977). There is a whiff of reductive physicalism: the mind will be automatically understood once we understand the brain (one never really hears how), keep on mapping and it will eventually get cognitive (but even water is not just H2O; Chang, 2012). The hope that meaning will emerge from the neural jungle, both for the mouse and for the neuroscientists studying it, is simply a naive philosophical commitment presented as an ensuing scientific fact. What would every single neural connection tell us about a broken heart or a Buddhist monk? Neuro-exceptionalism for mental matters is a myth, in the realm of religion (Thompson, 2020) as well as within science itself. The connectome is certainly not sufficient and, in many ways, probably not even necessary as an explainer of cognition (Barack and Krakauer, 2021). Not an epistemic foundation and even less a replacement for mind. Neural connections will not give us mice minds in the same way that quarks do not explain nor produce stock markets. Optimism and audacity are welcome, but conceit ultimately gives rise to concern. Climbing a tree (no matter how tall) is not the first step to get to the moon (Dreyfus, 2012).

Acknowledgments

Acknowledgements: I wish to thank Asif Ghazanfar, John Krakauer, Rupert Sheldrake and Carlos Sonnenschein for valuable discussions and critical comments. I am also grateful to anonymous reviewers and the editor for constructive suggestions.

Footnotes

  • The author declares no competing financial interests.

  • This work was funded by the Spanish Ministry of Science under grant RyC-2017-23599.

This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license, which permits unrestricted use, distribution and reproduction in any medium provided that the original work is properly attributed.

References

  1. ↵
    Abbott LF, Bock DD, Callaway EM, Denk W, Dulac C, Fairhall AL, Fiete I, Harris KM, Helmstaedter M, Jain V, Kasthuri N, LeCun Y, Lichtman JW, Littlewood PB, Luo L, Maunsell JHR, Reid RC, Rosen BR, Rubin GM, Sejnowski TJ, et al. (2020) The mind of a mouse. Cell 182:1372–1376. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2020.08.010 pmid:32946777
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  2. ↵
    Barack DL, Krakauer JW (2021) Two views on the cognitive brain. Nat Rev Neurosci, in press.
  3. ↵
    Bennet N (2013) Promising the world. Lancet 381:1616. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(13)61011-9
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  4. ↵
    Capek M (1971) Bergson and modern physics. A reinterpretation and re-evaluation. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.
  5. ↵
    Chang H (2012) Is water H2O? Evidence, realism and pluralism. Amstetrdam: Springer.
  6. ↵
    Chiel HJ, Beer RD (1997) The brain has a body: adaptive behavior emerges from interactions of nervous system, body and environment. Trends Neurosci 20:553–557. doi:10.1016/S0166-2236(97)01149-1
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  7. ↵
    Cisek P (2019) Resynthesizing behavior through phylogenetic refinement. Atten Percept Psychophys 81:2265–2287. doi:10.3758/s13414-019-01760-1 pmid:31161495
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  8. ↵
    Coletta L, Pagani M, Whitesell JD, Harris JA, Bernhardt B, Gozzi A (2020) Network structure of the mouse brain connectome with voxel resolution. Sci Adv 6:eabb7187. doi:10.1126/sciadv.abb7187
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  9. ↵
    Collins FS (2006) The language of god: a scientist presents evidence for belief. New York: Free Press.
  10. ↵
    Dreyfus HL (2012) A history of first step fallacies. Minds Mach 22:87–99. doi:10.1007/s11023-012-9276-0
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  11. ↵
    Eichler K, Li F, Litwin-Kumar A, Park Y, Andrade I, Schneider-Mizell CM, Saumweber T, Huser A, Eschbach C, Gerber B, Fetter RD, Truman JW, Priebe CE, Abbott LF, Thum AS, Zlatic M, Cardona A (2017) The complete connectome of a learning and memory centre in an insect brain. Nature 548:175–182. doi:10.1038/nature23455 pmid:28796202
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  12. ↵
    Flack JC (2017) Coarse-graining as a downward causation mechanism. Phil Trans R Soc A 375:20160338. doi:10.1098/rsta.2016.0338
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. ↵
    Forscher BK (1963) Chaos in the brickyard. Science 142:339. doi:10.1126/science.142.3590.339 pmid:17799464
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  14. ↵
    Gabriel M (2017) I am not a brain: philosophy of mind for the 21st Century. Cambridge: Polity.
  15. ↵
    Ghazanfar AA (2018) The brain is overrated. In: Think tank: forty neuroscientists explore the biological roots of human experience, pp 252–256. London: Yale University Press.
  16. ↵
    Gomez-Marin A (2017) Causal circuit explanations of behavior. Are necessity and sufficiency necessary and sufficient? In: Decoding neural circuit structure and function (Celik A and Wernet MF, eds). Cham: Springer.
  17. ↵
    Gomez-Marin A, Ghazanfar AA (2019) The life of behavior. Neuron 104:25–36. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2019.09.017 pmid:31600513
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  18. ↵
    Gunaratne CA, Sakura A, Katz PS (2017) Variations on a theme: species differences in synaptic connectivity do not predict central pattern generator activity. J Neurophysiol 118:1123–1132. doi:10.1152/jn.00203.2017 pmid:28539397
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  19. ↵
    Hadot P (2006) The veil of Isis: an essay on the history of the idea of nature. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  20. ↵
    Hagmann P (2005) From diffusion MRI to brain connectomics. PhD Thesis, Lausanne: École Polytechnique Fédérale de Lausanne.
  21. ↵
    Hall SS (2010) Revolution postponed: why the human genome project has been disappointing. Sci Am 303:60–67.
  22. ↵
    Hildebrand DGC, Cicconet M, Torres RM, Choi W, Quan TM, Moon J, Wetzel AW, Scott Champion A, Graham BJ, Randlett O, Plummer GS, Portugues R, Bianco IH, Saalfeld S, Baden AD, Lillaney K, Burns R, Vogelstein JT, Schier AF, Lee WCA, et al. (2017) Whole-brain serial-section electron microscopy in larval zebrafish. Nature 545:345–349. doi:10.1038/nature22356 pmid:28489821
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  23. ↵
    Hoel EP, Albantakis L, Tononi G (2013) Quantifying causal emergence shows that macro can beat micro. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 110:19790–19795. doi:10.1073/pnas.1314922110 pmid:24248356
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  24. ↵
    Hulse BK, Haberkern H, Franconville R, Turner-Evans DB, Takemura SY, Wolff T, Noorman M, Dreher M, Dan C, Parekh R, Hermundstad AM, Rubin GM, Jayaraman V (2020) A connectome of the Drosophila central complex reveals network motifs suitable for flexible navigation and context-dependent action selection. bioRxiv 413955. doi: 10.1101/2020.12.08.413955.doi:10.1101/2020.12.08.413955
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  25. ↵
    Jonas E, Kording KP (2017) Could a neuroscientist understand a microprocessor? PLoS Comput Biol 13:e1005268. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1005268 pmid:28081141
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  26. ↵
    Kay LE (2000) Who Wrote the Book of Life?: A History of the Genetic Code. Stanford University Press.
  27. ↵
    Krakauer JW, Ghazanfar AA, Gomez-Marin A, MacIver MA, Poeppel D (2017) Neuroscience needs behavior: correcting a reductionist bias. Neuron 93:480–490. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2016.12.041 pmid:28182904
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  28. ↵
    Laurent G (2016) Connectomics: a need for comparative studies. e-Neuroforum 7:54–55. doi:10.1007/s13295-016-0025-3
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  29. ↵
    Lazebnik Y (2002) Can a biologist fix a radio? Or, what I learned while studying apoptosis. Cancer Cell 2:179–182. doi:10.1016/S1535-6108(02)00133-2
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  30. ↵
    Lazebnik Y (2018) Who is Dr. Frankenstein? Or, what Professor Hayek and his friends have done to science, organisms. J Biol Sci 2:9–42.
    OpenUrl
  31. ↵
    Li F, Lindsey JW, Marin EC, Otto N, Dreher M, Dempsey G, Stark I, Bates AS, Pleijzier MW, Schlegel P, Nern A, Takemura SY, Eckstein N, Yang T, Francis A, Braun A, Parekh R, Costa M, Scheffer LK, Aso Y, et al. (2020) The connectome of the adult Drosophila mushroom body provides insights into function. Elife 9:e62576. doi:10.7554/eLife.62576
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  32. ↵
    Lichtman JW, Sanes JR (2008) Ome sweet ome: what can the genome tell us about the connectome? Curr Opin Neurobiol 18:346–353. doi:10.1016/j.conb.2008.08.010 pmid:18801435
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  33. ↵
    Lichtman JW, Pfister H, Shavit N (2014) The big data challenges of connectomics. Nat Neurosci 17:1448–1454. doi:10.1038/nn.3837 pmid:25349911
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  34. ↵
    Lu J, Tapia JC, White OL, Lichtman JW (2009) The interscutularis muscle connectome. PLoS Biol 7:e1000032. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1000032
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  35. ↵
    Marder E (2012) Neuromodulation of neuronal circuits: back to the future. Neuron 76:1–11. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2012.09.010 pmid:23040802
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  36. ↵
    Marder E, Bucher D (2007) Understanding circuit dynamics using the stomatogastric nervous system of lobsters and crabs. Annu Rev Physiol 69:291–316. doi:10.1146/annurev.physiol.69.031905.161516 pmid:17009928
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  37. ↵
    Marr D (1982) Vision: a computational approach. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  38. ↵
    Mehler DMA, Kording KP (2018) The lure of misleading causal statements in functional connectivity. arXiv 1812:e03363.
    OpenUrl
  39. ↵
    Morgan J, Lichtman J (2013) Why not connectomics? Nat Methods 10:494–500. doi:10.1038/nmeth.2480 pmid:23722208
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  40. ↵
    Nature (2011) Best is yet to come. Nature 470:140.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  41. ↵
    Niv Y (2020) On the primacy of behavioral research for understanding the brain. In: Current controversies in philosophy of cognitive science. Milton Park: Routledge.
  42. ↵
    Oh SW, Harris JA, Ng L, Winslow B, Cain N, Mihalas S, Wang Q, Lau C, Kuan L, Henry AM, Mortrud MT, Ouellette B, Nguyen TN, Sorensen SA, Slaughterbeck CR, Wakeman W, Li Y, Feng D, Ho A, Nicholas E, et al. (2014) A mesoscale connectome of the moue brain. Nature 508:207–214. doi:10.1038/nature13186 pmid:24695228
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  43. ↵
    Popper KR, Eccles JC (1977) The self and its brain: an argument for interactionism. Cham: Springer International.
  44. ↵
    Rosset C (2012) The real and its double. Calcutta: Seagull Books.
  45. ↵
    Scheffer LK, Xu CS, Januszewski M, Lu Z, Takemura SY, Hayworth KJ, Huang GB, Shinomiya K, Maitlin-Shepard J, Berg S, Clements J, Hubbard PM, Katz WT, Umayam L, Zhao T, Ackerman D, Blakely T, Bogovic J, Dolafi T, Kainmueller D, Kawase T, et al. (2020) A connectome and analysis of the adult Drosophila central brain. Elife 9:e57443. doi:10.7554/eLife.57443
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  46. ↵
    Science (2001) In their own words. Science 291:1196.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  47. ↵
    Seung S (2012) Connectome: how the brain’s wiring makes us who we are. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.
  48. ↵
    Sporns O, Tononi G, Kötter R (2005) The human connectome: a structural description of the human brain. PLoS Comput Biol 1:e42. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.0010042 pmid:16201007
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  49. ↵
    Theil S (2015) Why the human brain project went wrong – and how to fix it. Sci Am 313:36–42.
  50. ↵
    Thompson E (2020) Why I am not a Buddhist. London: Yale University Press.
  51. ↵
    Thompson E, Cosmelli D (2011) Brain in a vat or body in a world? Brainbound versus enactive views of experience. Philos Topics 39:163–180.
    OpenUrl
  52. ↵
    Vidal F (2016) Frankenstein’s brain: “the final touch.” Substance 45:88–117. doi:10.3368/ss.45.2.88
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  53. ↵
    von Uexküll J (1909) Umwelt un Innenwelt der Tiere [Umwelt and inner world of animals]. Berlin: Julius Springer.
  54. ↵
    White JG, Southgate E, Thomson JN, Brenner S (1986) The structure of the nervous system of the nematode Caenorhabditis elegans. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 314:1–340. doi:10.1098/rstb.1986.0056 pmid:22462104
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  55. ↵
    Winnubst J, Bas E, Ferreira TA, Wu Z, Economo MN, Edson P, Arthur BJ, Bruns C, Rokicki K, Schauder D, Olbris DJ, Murphy SD, Ackerman DG, Arshadi C, Baldwin P, Blake R, Elsayed A, Hasan M, Ramirez D, Dos Santos B, et al. (2019) Reconstruction of 1,000 projection neurons reveals new cell types and organization of long-range connectivity in the mouse brain. Cell 179:268–281. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2019.07.042 pmid:31495573
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  56. ↵
    Witvliet D, Mulcahy B, Mitchell JK, Meirovitch Y, Berger DR, Wu Y, Liu Y, Koh WX, Parvathala R, Holmyard D, Schalek RL, Shavit N, Chisholm AD, Lichtman JW, Samuel ADT, Zhen M (2020) Connectomes across development reveal principles of brain maturation in C. elegans. bioRxiv 066209. doi: 10.1101/2020.04.30.066209. doi: 10.1101/2020.04.30.066209
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  57. ↵
    Yoshihara M, Yoshihara M (2018) ‘Necessary and sufficient’ in biology is not necessarily necessary – confusions and erroneous conclusions resulting from misapplied logic in the field of biology, especially neuroscience. J Neurogenet 32:53–64. doi:10.1080/01677063.2018.1468443 pmid:29757057
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  58. ↵
    Zheng Z, Lauritzen JS, Perlman E, Robinson CG, Nichols M, Milkie D, Torrens O, Price J, Fisher CB, Sharifi N, Calle-Schuler SA, Kmecova L, Ali IJ, Karsh B, Trautman ET, Bogovic JA, Hanslovsky P, Jefferis GSXE, Kazhdan M, Khairy K, et al. (2018) A complete electron microscopy volume of the brain of adult Drosophila melanogaster. Cell 174:730–743. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2018.06.019 pmid:30033368
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed

Synthesis

Reviewing Editor: Erica Glasper, University of Maryland

Decisions are customarily a result of the Reviewing Editor and the peer reviewers coming together and discussing their recommendations until a consensus is reached. When revisions are invited, a fact-based synthesis statement explaining their decision and outlining what is needed to prepare a revision will be listed below. The following reviewer(s) agreed to reveal their identity: Federico Adolfi.

Manuscript Title: Nevermind

Manuscript #: eN-COM-0521-20

Synthesis

Within this commentary lies a detailed assessment of the value of connectome mapping strategies within the field of neuroscience. This article was reviewed by two respected leaders in the field of neuroscience and each concluded that the article was well-written, thought -provoking, and shed a light on the many challenges that surround performing these types of investigations, as well as pinpointed some limitations in our ability to draw conclusions from these investigations. The reviewers note that this article will help the larger neuroscience community avoid many epistemic pitfalls due to the authors important and necessary pushback against implicit, reductive assumptions in neuroscience-adjacent fields. Despite this overall enthusiasm, both reviewers agreed that some statements were " overly subjective in nature and not necessary to support the author’s main arguments." The author is encouraged to revise or remove the statements (these statements can be found in italics below.

1) Subjective Statements:

a) "But too soon we come across the usual "promissory notes" using the usual rhetoric based on "filler verbs" (underly, determine, unravel) and "killer adjectives" (transformative, disruptive, mechanistic)."

i) This sentence highlights verbs and adjectives that are often found in scientific literature. The piece suggests that the use of these terms leads to unobtainable goals. However, in many instances, research has been shown to find factors that underlie or determine a certain behavior, or provide a mechanistic understanding. Thus, the negation of these terms draws away from the point that the author is trying to make in the paper.

b) "Who knows? To issue promissory notes on top of promissory notes is a bit too much."

i) This statement is very subjective and not necessary - e.g., what qualifies as being ‘too much’?

c) Line 95: The contention that examining synaptic connections is done by ‘uneducated’ based on an ‘act of faith’ is not warranted. Thus, this sentence should be revised accordingly with removal of these statements.

d) Some statements could be interpreted as value judgements and should be rephrased and substantiated. The risk of leaving the following statements as is could be viewed as antagonizing and polarizing:

i) "This is...unsophisticated futurology."

ii) "The first sentence...is delicious"

iii) "the (uneducated) guess..."

2) The lack of citations and a reference list undermines the weight and value of the arguments. A reader who is not already familiar with the relevant literature may miss the connections that are being made. Citations should be added throughout the article to assist the reader with connecting this well-written critique to the relevant literature. This will help to make the manuscript more educational. This is of particular importance for researchers in computational cognitive neuroscience with backgrounds that are more tech-heavy that lack the background knowledge against a bottom-up, big data approach that is often standard in other areas of neuroscience. Several criticisms, in the absence of support by referencing and quoting, can easily be misinterpreted as attacking a straw-man claim that nobody holds. For example,

a) "one does not get circuit function from circuit structure".

i) It would be hard to get somebody to agree with the extreme opposite, so there is no need to contradict such a hypothetical statement. Instead, one can think of particular cases where the opposite statement holds - where indeed structure has hinted at function - and formulate a critique of that more nuanced view which propels some scientists’ reductionist ideas in practice.

b) One reviewer suggests the "critique needs to point to passages in the original commentary or other parts of the literature where a relative consensus around a false or fallible claim lies. If it cannot be shown directly with quotations, which is perfectly possible in the case of implicit assumptions, then it needs to be argued by, for example, pointing to scientists’ actions stemming from flawed assumptions"

3) The author is encouraged to spell out counterarguments to claims such as this from the target commentary:

a) "These data are generating many hypotheses that are already being put to the test with new experiments. In areas of the fly brain that have seen particularly intense connectomic study, such as the mushroom body, central complex, and visual system, it is increasingly difficult to envision studies that ignore the insights generated by studying their connectomes."

4) Early career researcher may find of particular interest the identification of misplaced assumptions in the section "A path toward designing non-biological thinking systems". Given the hype surrounding AI research, this field if particularly vulnerable in terms of harboring flawed implicit assumptions about how we gain knowledge of how intelligent systems work. The author is encouraged to address the following questions:

a) Are there any mischaracterizations behind the view that "Neuroscience has thus already had a profound impact on the development of AI."?

b) Has this occurred in a bottom-up way as many proponents like to portray it?

c) How exactly is the full connectome a "blueprint for cognitive computing"?

i) It seems this claim in the section mentioned above is particularly weak and unsubstantiated in the target commentary.

5) The author is encouraged to change the manuscript title. The title, as it stands, may turn away readers due to its dismissiveness. The purpose of this commentary is to engage the audience and to convince them to consider your point of view. The title alone could lead our audience to ignore the article altogether.

6) A typo was found here: "in the pursuit of understand"

Back to top

In this issue

eneuro: 8 (2)
eNeuro
Vol. 8, Issue 2
March/April 2021
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author
  • Ed Board (PDF)
Email

Thank you for sharing this eNeuro article.

NOTE: We request your email address only to inform the recipient that it was you who recommended this article, and that it is not junk mail. We do not retain these email addresses.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Promisomics and the Short-Circuiting of Mind
(Your Name) has forwarded a page to you from eNeuro
(Your Name) thought you would be interested in this article in eNeuro.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Print
View Full Page PDF
Citation Tools
Promisomics and the Short-Circuiting of Mind
Alex Gomez-Marin
eNeuro 1 March 2021, 8 (2) ENEURO.0521-20.2021; DOI: 10.1523/ENEURO.0521-20.2021

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Respond to this article
Share
Promisomics and the Short-Circuiting of Mind
Alex Gomez-Marin
eNeuro 1 March 2021, 8 (2) ENEURO.0521-20.2021; DOI: 10.1523/ENEURO.0521-20.2021
del.icio.us logo Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Significance Statement
    • Acknowledgments
    • Footnotes
    • References
    • Synthesis
  • Info & Metrics
  • eLetters
  • PDF

Keywords

  • cognition
  • connectomics
  • levels of analysis
  • promissory materialism

Responses to this article

Respond to this article

Jump to comment:

No eLetters have been published for this article.

Related Articles

Cited By...

More in this TOC Section

Commentary

  • Some Tips for Writing Science
  • COVID-19 Deterred Career Path of Our Undergraduate Neuroscience Students: Educators’ Perspective
  • Remembering Hirsh Cohen and His Role in Developing Computational Neuroscience
Show more Commentary

Cognition and Behavior

  • Effects of cortical FoxP1 knockdowns on learned song preference in female zebra finches
  • The genetic architectures of functional and structural connectivity properties within cerebral resting-state networks
  • Nonlinear Theta-Gamma Coupling between the Anterior Thalamus and Hippocampus Increases as a Function of Running Speed
Show more Cognition and Behavior

Subjects

  • Cognition and Behavior
  • Commentaries

  • Home
  • Alerts
  • Visit Society for Neuroscience on Facebook
  • Follow Society for Neuroscience on Twitter
  • Follow Society for Neuroscience on LinkedIn
  • Visit Society for Neuroscience on Youtube
  • Follow our RSS feeds

Content

  • Early Release
  • Current Issue
  • Latest Articles
  • Issue Archive
  • Blog
  • Browse by Topic

Information

  • For Authors
  • For the Media

About

  • About the Journal
  • Editorial Board
  • Privacy Policy
  • Contact
  • Feedback
(eNeuro logo)
(SfN logo)

Copyright © 2023 by the Society for Neuroscience.
eNeuro eISSN: 2373-2822

The ideas and opinions expressed in eNeuro do not necessarily reflect those of SfN or the eNeuro Editorial Board. Publication of an advertisement or other product mention in eNeuro should not be construed as an endorsement of the manufacturer’s claims. SfN does not assume any responsibility for any injury and/or damage to persons or property arising from or related to any use of any material contained in eNeuro.